Reeve's book explores the epistemological, metaphysical & psychological foundations of the Nicomachean Ethics. Reversing current orthodoxy, he argues that scientific knowledge (episteme) is possible in ethics, that dialectic & understanding (nous) play the same role in ethics as in an Aristotelian science, & that the distinctive role of practical wisdom (phronesis) is to use the knowledge of universals provided by science, dialectic & understanding so as to best promote happiness (eudaimonia) in particular circumstances & to ensure a happy life. Turning to happiness itself, he develops an account of Aristotle's views on ends & functions, exposing their 2fold nature. He argues that the activation of theoretical wisdom is primary happiness, & that the activation of practical wisdom--when it's for the sake of primary happiness--is happiness of a 2ndary kind. He ends with an account of the virtues of character, external goods & friends, & their place in the happy life.
C. D. C. Reeve is a philosophy professor at the University of North Carolina at Chapel Hill. He works primarily in Ancient Greek philosophy, especially Plato and Aristotle. He is also interested in philosophy generally, and has published work in the philosophy of sex and love, and on film. He has also translated many Ancient Greek texts, mostly by Plato and Aristotle.
Practices of Reason is a sympathetic exposition of the arguments of the Nichomachean Ethics within the context of Aristotle's entire corpus. It is, first and foremost, a study of argument, both as regards the general, formal method of dialectic and the particulars of Peripatetic ethics. It is not a study of texts, except insofar as ambiguities allow for various translations. In such cases Reeve is careful to save appearances by adopting interpretations most conducive to his heuristic belief that Aristotle is coherent. There is no mention of textual provenance or transmission; no discussion of historical or sociological context; no source, redaction or form criticism. There is no sense conveyed of Aristotle as an historical personage. As in the later Middle Ages, he is again "the Philosopher," a timeless persona.
Whether or not Reeve's arguments work can be examined on two levels. Ideally, the historian of ancient philosophy might evaluate them as a contribution to Aristotle studies. The non-specialist, however, can do little more than deal with Reeve, analyzing his moves, his treatment of selected passages. The graduate student of philosophy might thereby be moved to return to the classical text, to take it--and ancient thought--more seriously than hitherto.
Reeve does succeed in portraying Aristotle as a relevant thinker, particularly as regards the employment of dialectic. Without emphasizing it until his conclusion, Reeve takes the method seriously enough to use it himself, seeing it as a practical means of combining the work of philosophy with that of the other sciences. Philosophy is legitimated as a means of resolving the perplexities, the aporiai, generated by their respective teachings, their endoxa. This, of course, is in keeping with prevailing contemporary views of the discipline.
The older view, however, while including the analysis of propositions, was broader than this. The Ethics constitutes a portion of an answer to the question of living. What is the good life? Simply stated, the best life is one founded upon, and responsible to, a practicable social order allowing contemplative study. The final end, the telos of existence is nous knowing itself, human self-recognition in the transcendence of mortal contingency. But in Reeve's view:
". . . and it is surely one that will meet with little opposition, science and dialectic have not just taken these Aristotelian conclusions hostage, they have decisively killed them off. No one now believes that everything in the world is trying to become as much like Aristotle's god as possible, or, indeed, that there is such a god for them all to try to become like. No one believes, therefore, that study or the contemplation of that god can possibly be primary eudaimonia or what, so to speak, human life is all about. A major doctrine of the Ethics--if I am right the major doctrine--has therefore been falsified by science and dialectic and become incredible."
Given the relatively small claims made for Aristotle's Prime Mover in comparison to those made for other, much more popular conceptions, this remark is itself incredible. Have Judaism, Christianity and Islam been decisively killed off--or just the Aristotelian contributions to them? Or is it simply that modern conceptions of philosophy, of human being, are enervated?